CAN CONSTITUTIVE RULES CREATE A PRACTICE?
¿Las reglas constitutivas pueden crear una práctica?
Giuseppe Lorini
Università degli Studi di Cagliari - Italia
lorini@unica.it
Recibido: marzo 2012 aprobado: abril 2012
ABSTRACT
The author investigates the role of constitutive rules in the construction of social reality. He denies that constitutive rules are a sufficient condition of a practice such as a chess game. To create a new practice with rules, it is necessary that there already be the grammar of this practice, that is, the sense of this practice (for example, the sense of game). It is the grammar of a practice and not its constitutive rules that determines the nature of a practice. The sense of a practice cannot be created by constitutive rules.
Key words: constitutive rules, practice, social ontology, institutional fact.
RESUMEN
El autor investiga el papel desarrollado por las reglas constitutivas en la construcción de la realidad social. En particular, niega que, por jemplo, las reglas constitutivas del ajedrez sean condición suficiente de la práctica llamada juego del ajedrez. Para crear una nueva práctica, se necesita también la existencia de la gramática de esa práctica, o sea el sentido mismo de la práctica (por ejemplo: el sentido de juego). Es la gramática de una práctica (y no las reglas constitutivas) la que determina la naturaleza de la práctica misma. El sentido de una práctica no puede ser creado por las reglas constitutivas.
Palabras clave: reglas constitutivas, práctica, ontología social, hecho institucional.
Constitutive Rules and Sense of Game
This essay concerns social ontology. In social ontology, a fundamental distinction is that (proposed by the American philosopher John R. Searle) between brute facts and institutional facts.
For Searle (1969, 51), institutional facts are facts which, unlike brute facts, presuppose the existence of certain human "institutions". The adjective 'institutional' that Searle uses to qualify kind of fact derives from this definition of institutional facts.
If one ignores this distinction one may commit the error of confusing institutional status (like being a Lord-Mayor, Judge and Bishop) and objects that are only indicators of status. Jonathan Swift (1960, 283) describes this confusion genially in the following way: "These animals, which are vulgarly called suits of clothes, or dressed, do according to certain compositions receive different appellations. If one of them be trimmed up with a gold chain, and a red gown, and a white rod, and a great horse, it is called a Lord-Mayor; if certain ermines and furs be placed in a certain position, we style them a Judge, and so an apt conjunction of lawn and black satin we entitled a Bishop".
In order to characterize the concept of institutional fact and to distinguish institutional facts from brute facts, Searle uses the concept of a "constitutive rule". In fact, for Searle (1969, 51), "institutions" are systems of constitutive rules.
Searle distinguishes two different sorts of rules: regulative rules and constitutive rules. For Searle (1969, 34), "regulative rules regulate a preexisting activity, an activity whose existence is logically independent of the rules", whereas "constitutive rules constitute [...] an activity the existence of which is logically dependent on the rules". For example, "the rules of football or chess [...] do not merely regulate playing football or chess, but as it were they create the very possibility of playing such games".
My point of departure is the thesis that constitutive rules create the possibility of new forms of behavior. The question that I ask in the present essay is: It is really true that a new (type of) institutional activity can be created only by constitutive rules? This essay investigates the way in which an institutional activity is created by means of constitutive rules, but also the limits and the conditions of the creation of institutional activities by constitutive rules. In other words, the question is, Are the constitutive rules of a practice a necessary and sufficient condition of the type of practice that is its object?1
My answer is this: constitutive rules can create the possibility of new forms of behavior (a new rule-constituted activity), but they can not themselves create a new practice. They can not be a necessary and sufficient condition of a practice.
In order to explain and demonstrate this thesis, I begin by looking at the thesis argued for Searle (1969, 33-34):
The activity of playing chess is constituted by acting in accordance with the appropriate rules.
Is it true, however, that the activity of playing chess consists in acting in accordance with the constitutive rules of chess? In other words, does the activity of playing chess consist in acting in accordance with the constitutive rules that constitute the possible moves and the values of the chess pieces?
('Constitutive rules of chess' I understand to be those rules that are specific to the game of chess; in other terms, all the rules that define the possible moves in the game and the value of chess pieces.2 It is those rules that distinguish the game of chess from soccer or checkers.)
Another philosopher, Hubert Schwyzer has criticized the Searle's thesis. Schwyzer doesn't deny that chess is a game played by acting in conformity to the rules of the game. In other words, Schwyzer doesn't deny that the game of chess is a rule-governed activity. What he denies is:
first, that the sense of game characterising the activity of playing chess derives from acting in conformity to the rules of the game;
second, that the sense of game characterising the institution called 'chess' is constituted by the rules of chess.
(i) First, Schwyzer denies that the sense of game characterising the activity of playing chess consists in acting in conformity to the rules of chess:
For Schwyzer (1969, 464), "playing chess does not consist in acting in accordance with the rules. The rules do not explicate the concept of playing chess; they do not establish what it is to play chess." Acting in accordance with these rules isn't a sufficient condition for the fact that you are playing chess.
An similar observation occurs in Josef Schächter (1935). Schächter argues that it is not sufficient to act according to the rules of chess to play chess. In the case of a person who practices the rules of chess with his instructor, these two people are not playing chess. In Schächter's terminology, they are not "using" the rules, but only demonstrating them. Schächter writes:
(ii) Second, Schwyzer denies, also, that the sense of game characterising the game of chess is constituted by the rules of chess. As Schwyzer writes:
That chess is a game is in no way a rule of the game (SCHWYZER 1969, 463).
The problem here is: in what does the sense of game of an activity like playing chess consist?
Chess-like Game vs. Chess-like Rite
Schwyzer explains and proves the apparently counterintuitive thesis that the sense of game isn't intrinsic to the activity constituted by the constitutive rules of chess, proposing a mental experiment:
Continuing with his mental experiment, Schwyzer imagines that, on returning to home, he shows his own chess set to his host and he asks him to play chess. But here is the surprising reaction of his host to this request:
Why did Schwyzer's host react in this way to the simple request to play chess? Schwyzer understands the reason of this excessive reaction when his host explains to him what the practice of chess consists of in Ruritania:
Then, to the Schwyzer's question whether the white should always win, the host, once more shocked, answers in this way:
Here the misunderstanding is revealed: in Ruritania, chess is not a game, but a religious rite that is enacted only once a year by the priest of the community.4 The rite of chess is not a form of competition: in the rite of chess, you can't win or loose, because victory and defeat don't compose the grammar of the rite.
Consequently, for the grammar of rite, in Ruritania's chess it doesn't make sense to talk of strategy.
In this mental experiment, Schwyzer focuses on the fact that the differences between the game of chess and the rite of chess are not determined by the constitutive rules of chess. Indeed, the activity of the two practices (rite of chess and game of chess) is governed by the same rules: the constitutive rules of chess.
But where then lies the difference between the two practices?
(i) The difference between the two practices doesn't appear on the brute level of description of the action. It is not perceivable in the observation of mere physical activities that compose the two practices.
Additionally, the difference between the two practices doesn't consist even in mental events in the minds of the players. Schwyzer writes:
(ii) The difference between the two practices doesn't appear even to the institutional level of description of the action. Indeed, the two practices, sharing the same system of rules, necessarily also share the same institutional support consisting in an activity according the constitutive rules of chess.
(iii) Instead, the difference between the two practices consists in the different role, in the different value, that the activity has in the everyday life of those who practice it:
For Schwyzer, it is the different grammar of the two activities that distinguishes the game of chess from the rite of chess. It is the grammar of a practice and not its constitutive rules that determines its nature, and consequently its sense of rite or its sense of game:
Schwyzer (1969, 463) believes that the fact "that chess is a game is in no way a rule of the game". It is a grammatical proposition.5 In this regard, he writes:
Schwyzer further argues:
In the same way, the fact that chess presuppose skill belongs to the grammar of chess.
Similarly, it is because of its grammar that the rite of chess is different from the game of chess. The rite of chess, indeed, unlike the game of chess, is not a form of competition and, so, it doesn't make sense to talk in the rite of chess about victory and defeat, or even strategy.
For Schwyzer, the word 'grammar' in the phrase 'grammar of chess' has a very similar meaning to the term 'grammar' used in the ordinary schoolbook grammar. Similarly the grammar as a theory of syntax means that 'children' is a noun and 'play' is a verb and that it is meaningful to write 'The children play', but not 'The play children'; the grammar of a practice means that chess is a competition, and it means that it makes sense to say certain things with regard to chess, but not with regard to other practices.
Schwyzer's observation suggests that there is a level of institutional action (the level of the activity that has a sense of a practice, like a sense of game or a sense of rite), where the constitutive rules don't work.
With regard to the distinction between the concept of activity constituted by rules and the concept of practice, it is clear that acting in accordance with the rules of chess isn't sufficient, in order to play chess, in the same way that acting in accordance with the rules of soccer isn't sufficient in order to play soccer.
Rule-Constituted Activity vs. Practice
In order to prove that institutional activities and institutions are not mere rule-constituted activities, Schwyzer invents a new rule-governed activity that isn't a practice: X-ing. Schwyzer writes:
X-ing is a rule-governed activity, i.e. an activity whose nature consists in acting in conformity to its constitutive rules. Asks Schwyzer:
What is X-ing? An activity according to these rules (SCHWYZER 1969, 464).
But this activity has no other senses than this. It isn't a game or a rite. It isn't a way of doing something like a will is a "way of" distributing one's property after one's death. For Schwyzer, X-ing is a mere rule-governed activity that isn't a practice.
For Schwyzer, X-ing is not a practice for three different reasons.
(i) First, "X-ing hasn't a grammar" (Schwyzer 1969, 465). There aren't grammatical propositions on the nature of X-ing. Recovering the philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein, Schwyzer (1969, 454) defines the grammar of an activity as that "which makes it an activity of that kind". The grammar is the place of sense (for instance, sense of rite or sense of game) that conditions the possibility of being of a practice.
(ii) Second, there isn't any situation that counts as an appropriate situation to engage in X-ing (Schwyzer 1969, 465).
(iii) Third, X-ing hasn't any other sense than the sense of acting in accordance with its rules:
Unlike X-ing, chess is, instead, an example of a rule-governed activity that is also a practice. Chess is an example of an activity that can be performed only by acting in accordance with constitutive rules, but whose sense doesn't exhaust itself in a simple behaviour that conforms to constitutive rules. Chess is a game, but that it is a game is not abducible by the constitutive rules of the game. The rules of chess don't permit the understanding of the sense of this activity. The sense of this activity transcends those rules that constitute the possibility of the game.
I now return to the initial question posed in this essay: Does the activity of playing chess consist in acting in accordance with the constitutive rules of chess?
My answer is negative. I believe playing chess doesn't consist only in acting in conformity to the rules of chess. It's obvious that chess is a game played by acting in conformity to its rules. It's impossible to play chess without the rules of chess. But it's no less true that to move in accordance to the rules of chess is not necessarily to play chess. A person who moves mechanically chess pieces without a strategy or without the goal of checkmate, isn't playing chess. It's even possible, following the rules of chess, to perform an activity totally different from and also grammatically incompatible with the game of chess, such as the rite of chess described by Schwyzer.
Averroës' Impossible Research
An epistemical thesis corresponds to my ontological thesis about the nature of institutional activity: if you don't know the grammar of a practice, you can't understand what that practice is, even if you know very well the constitutive rules of that practice.
For instance, if you don't understand what a game is, if you don't know the grammar of "game", you can't understand what a game of chess is, even if you know very well the rules of chess.
Curiously, a similar kind of impossibility is described in a short story by Jorge Luis Borges: La busca de Averroes. In this short story, Borges tells us of an impossible research, the research of Averroës. Averroës tried to translate the Poetics of Aristotle, but being closed within the limits of Islam culture, and not knowing theatre, he couldn't understand the meaning of the two terms 'tragedy' and 'comedy'.
Footnotes
1The idea that they are rules which create new possibilities of action can already be found in the work of the Polish legal philosopher Czeslaw Znamierowski (1924). (Cf Giuseppe Lorini 2000, 69-81).References
BORGES, Jorge Luis (1981). Obras completas. Buenos Aires, Emecé.
CONTE, Amedeo G. (1988). Eidos. An Essay on Constitutive Rules. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 11: 251-257.
LÉVI-STRAUSS, Claude (1962). La pensée sauvage. Paris, Plon.
LORINI, Giuseppe (2000). Dimensioni giuridiche dell'istituzionale. Padua, CEDAM.
LORINI, Giuseppe (2008). Oggetto e atto. Torino, Giappichelli.
MILLER, Dolores (1983). Constitutive Rules and Essential Rules. Philosophical Studies 39: 183-197.
ROVERSI, Corrado (2007). Pragmatica delle regole costitutive. Bologna, GEDIT.
SCHÄCHTER, Josef (1935). Prolegomena zu einer kritischen Grammatik. Wien, Julius Springer.
SCHWYZER, Hubert (1969). Rules and Practices. The Philosophical Review 78: 451-467.
SEARLE, John Rogers (1969). Speech Acts. An Essay in the Philosophy of Language. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
SEARLE, John Rogers (1995). The Construction of Social Reality. New York, Free Press.
SEARLE, John Rogers (2010). Making the social world: the structure of human civilization. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
SWIFT, Jonathan (1960). A Tale of a Tub. In Swift, Jonathan, A Tale of a Tub with Other Early Works (1696-1707). Ed. Louis A. Landa, 241-353. Oxford, Blackwell.
WITTGENSTEIN, Ludwig (1953). Philosophical Investigations. Oxford, Blackwell.
WITTGENSTEIN, Ludwig (1969). Philosophische Grammatik. Ed. Rush Rhees. Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
ZLANIEC, Wojciech (1992). Fathers, Kings and Promises. Husserl and Reinach on the A Priori. Husserl Studies 9: 147-177.
ZNAMIEROWSKI, Czeslaw (1924). Podstawowe pojêcia teorji prawa. I. Poznañ, Fiszer i Majewski.